Points of Controversy
OR
Subjects of Discourse
BEING A TRANSLATION OF THE KATHAVATTHU
FROM THE ABHIDHAMMA-PITAKA
BY
SHWE ZAN AUNG, B.A
AND
MRS. RHYS DAVIDS, M.A
9 . SANGAHA: CLASSIFICATION.
(VII. 1, p. 195.)
This little discourse is interesting for its bearing on the
historic European controversy between Universals and
Particulars, dating from Herakleitus and Parmenides, two
and a half centuries before the date of our work, with
the problems: How can the Many be One ? How can the
One be in the Many ? Both the Kathavatthu and its
Commentary oppose the limiting of groupable things to
mental facts. If certain things be counted one by one,
they reach a totality (gananag gacchanti) , say, a totality
of five. This total needs a generic concept to express itself.
If the five units happen to possess common, say, bovine,
attributes, we apply the concept 'bullocks,' 'cows.' So
with the concept' dog,' which holds together all individuals
possessing canine attributes. Again, if we were to count by
groups, say, three bullocks and three dogs, the units would
reach the same total. But we should require a more
general, a ' higher' concept—' animal,' or the like—to
include both species. Now whether we have relatively
homogeneous units under a general notion, or relatively
heterogeneous groups under a wider notion, they reach
hereby an abridged statement (uddesAIJ gacchanti )
in the economy of thought.
1
The Theravadin, as we have recorded, does not approve
of the crude rope simile, because the material bond is
necessarily different from the mental concept, and the
term, physical and mental, binding units together. Neither
does he altogether disapprove of the simile, since language,
rooted in sense-experience, compels us to illustrate mental
processes by material phenomena.
10. PARIBHOGA : UTILITY.
(VII. 5.)
Paribhoga is enjoyment. Utility, as ethicists and
economists use the term, is enjoyability, positive benefit.
1
It is interesting to compare the ganana (number), sangah a
(class), uddes a (abridged statement), of fcssa's Katha-vatthu with
such disquisitions on number, class, general term, as that by Mr.
Bertrand Russell in his examination of Frege's Qrundlagen der
Arithmetic in ' Our Knowledge of the External World,', p. 201 L
And the opponents claim that ' there is merit consisting in
the fact, not that the good deed was done with benevolent
intention, but that the deed done is bestowing enjoyment
or utility.' The orthodox argument seeks only to prove the
unsoundness of this way of reckoning merit (for the doer),
either on grounds of psychological process [1] or of ethics
[2, 3]. His own position, stated positively, is that the
donor's will (c e t a n a) or intention is the only standard,
criterion, ultimate court of appeal, by which to judge of
the merit (to himself) o f his act. Posterity may bless him
for utility accruing to it. But if he gave as a benefactor
malgre lui, he will in future be, not better, but worse off .
11 . PACCAYA : CORRELATION.
(XV. 1, 2.)
The word paccaya,
1
used in popular diction, together
with hetu , for ' cause
5
or ' reason why,' is closely akin to
our
4
relation.' lie and pati (p a c c a y a is contracted from
pati-a y a) are coincident in meaning. Ay a is a causative
form of i, ' to go,' giving ' go back' for the Latin [re]latus,
£
carry back.' Now£
relation,' as theory of' things as having
to do with each other,' put into the most general terms
possible, includes the class called causal relation, viz.,
things as related by way of cause-effect. But paccaya ,
as relation, implies that, for Buddhist philosophy, all modes
of relation have causal significance, though the causal
efficacy, as power to produce the effect , may be absent.
To understand this we must consider everything, not as
statically existing, but as 'happening,' or 'event.' We
may then go on to define paccaya as an event which
helps to account for the happening of the paccayup-
panna, ie., the effect , or 'what-has-happened-through-the-
paccaya. ' These two terms are thus ? related.' Dropping
our notion of efficient cause (A as having power to pro-
duce B), and holding to the ' helping to happen ' notion,
1
Pronounce pach-chaya with the same cadence as ' bachelor.'
we see this recognized in the definition of paccay a as
' that which was the essential mark of helping, of working
up to (upakaraka), ' namely, to a given happening.
1
It
may not produce, or alone bring to pass, that happening ;
but it is concerned therewith.
Calling it the paccaya , A, and the other term, the
other happening, B, the paccayuppanna , and referring
to the twenty-four classes of relations distinguished in
Abhidhamma, A may 4
help ' as being ' contiguous,' 're-
peated,' a
f i
dominant' circumstance, or by £
leading towards,'
as ' path ' (magga-paccaya ) or means. But only such
a paccay a as
£
will '(cetana ) related, as ' karma,'
2
to a
result (v i p a k a), is adequate to produce, or to cause that
result B.
In the expression idappaccayata—' conditionedness
of this—' this' (ida) refers to B, but the compound refers
to A: A is the 'paccaya-of-£/us." The abstract form
is only the philosophic way of expressing paccaya .
The terms discussed above — dhamma-thitata ,
dhamma-niyamata—ar e synonymous with ida p -
paccayata , and mean B is established through A, is
fixed through A. This does not mean ' is produced (solely)
by A,' but only ' happens whenever A happens,' and
' happens because, inter alia, A happens.' In other words,
by a constant relation between A and B, we are enabled to
infer the happening of B from the happening of A.
The classification of relations by the Hon. B. Russell,
referred to on p. 294, n. 3, is as follows:—'A relation is
symmetrical if, whenever it holds between A and B, it also
holds between B and A;' asymmetrical, 'if it does not hold
between B and A.' But of yet greater interest is it to see
this learned author, ignorant to all appearances of perhaps
one subject only—Buddhist philosophy—generalizing the
whole concept of causality in terms of relations, namely,
'that what is constant in a causal law is not ' A or B,
1
Buddhist Psychology, London, 1914, p. 194 f .
2
In the mode called janaka-kamma (reproductive karma).
See Compendium, loo cit.
' but the relation between A and B . . . that a causal law
involves not one datum, but many, and that the general
scheme of a causal law will be ' Whenever things occur in
certain relations to each other, another thing, B, having a
fixed relation to those A's, will occur in a certain time-
relation to them 5
(op. cit., 215 f.). Or again, ' The law of
causation . . . may be enunciated as follows :—There are
certain invariable relations between different events,' etc.
(p. 221). These ' invariable relations ' are, for Buddhists,
the twenty-four kinds of paccayas , including the time-
relation, which are conceived, not as efficient causes, but as
4
events' which in happening ' help' to bring about the
correlated event called paccayuppanna .
12 . TIME AND SPACE.
In the Abhidhmiappadipika-suct time is defined under
three aspects:—
1. ' Time is a concept by which the terms of life, etc., are
cpunted or reckoned.
2. ' Time is that " passing by " reckoned as " so much has
passed," etc.
3. 'Time is eventuation or happening, there being no
such thing as time exempt from events."
The second aspect refers to the fact of change or imper-
manence; the third brings up the fact of perpetual becom-
ing. Prom perpetual becoming we get our idea of abstract
time (maha-kala), which is eternal, and lacks the com-
mon distinction of past, present, future, but which, to adopt
M. Bergson's phraseology, 'looked at from the point o f view
of multiplicity, . . disintegrates into a powder of moments,
none of which endures.'
2
. . .
1
For the general reader we may state that this valuable book, by
the venerable scholar Subhuti Maha-Thera, published at Colombo
1893, is an Index and Corny, on a work on Pali nouns, written by the
rammarian Moggallana in the twelfth century A.D.
2
Introd. to Metaphysics, 51
Now it is clear from the Kathavatthi
1
that, for Budd-
hism, time-distinctions have no objective existence of their
own, and that reality is confined to the present. The
past reality has perished; the future reality is not yet
become. And when Buddhist doctrine says that reality is
present, both these terms refer to one and the same thing
per se. "When this gives up its reality, it gives up its
presence; when it gives up being present, it ceases to be
real.
2
Things in time are not immutably fixed.
3
In Ledi Sadaw's
words:—As in our present state there is, so in our past has
there been, so in the future will there be, just a succession
of purely phenomenal happenings, proceedings, consisting
solely of arisings and ceasings, hard to discern . . . because
the procedure is ever obscured by our notion of continuity.'
4
Thus they who have not penetrated reality c
see only a
continuous and static condition in these phenomena.'
5
Now each momentary state or uprising of mind6
is logically
complex and analyzable, but psychologically, actually, a
simple indivisible process. There is a succession of these
states, and their orderly procession is due to the natural
uniformity of mental sequence—the Chitta-niyama.
7
And they present a continuous spectrum of mind in which
one state shades of f into another, laterally and lineally, so
that it is hard to say ' where,' or when one ends and the
other begins.
The laws or principles discernible in these mental con-
tinua of the Chitta-niyama are, according to Buddhist
philosophy, five of the twenty - four casual relations
(paccaya) , to wit, 'contiguity,' immediate contiguity
(in time), absence, abeyance, sufficing condition. Ex-
plained without such technicalities, the past state, albeit
1
See I. 6-8.
2
See I. 6, § 5.
3
See I. 10.
4
' Some Points of Buddbist Doctrine,' JPTS, 1918-14, p. 121.
5
Ibid., 155..
6
Ekakkhanika-cittuppada,
7
See Mrs. Rh. D., Buddhism, 1912, p. 119, and Ledi Sadaw's
'Expositions' {Buddhist Beview, October, 1915).
it is absent, gone, has become wrought up into its imme-
diate successor, the present state, as a new whole. These
five are compared to the five strands of a thread on which
are strung the pearls of a necklace.
1
But each indivisible
whole was real only while it lasted.
Matter, no less than mind, is logically resolved into
different qualities, which we group, classify, explain. But
nature gives us simple, indivisible wholes, qualities mutu-
ally inseparable, even in a dual existence such as that of
intelligent organisms. The whole is actually indivisible,
body and mind being inseparable.
Now what time is to life, space is to matter. Space, like
time, is a permanent concept or mental construction, which
constitutes a sufficing condition for the movement o f bodies.
It is void, unperceivable, without objective reality.
13 . ACCANTA : FINALITY.
(XIX. 7.)
Accant a is ati-anta:
2
beyond the end, or the very
last. Like eka n ta, it is rendered by Burmese translators
' true/ and for this reason : The only assurance we get
from science that the sun will rise to-morrow, and at
a given time, is our belief in the uniformity of Nature,
a belief established by past observation yielding no excep-
tion to the rule. The belief amounts, as we say, to a moral
certainty—i.e., we can act upon it. But since, for all we know,
some unforeseen force may divert the relative positions of
sun and earth, the uniformity of physical nature is not an
order of things which has reached finality in certainty. In
other words, it is not ' true ' absolutely.
1
Cf . Compendium, Mrs. Eh. D., Buddhist Psychology,
1914, p. 194 i
2
This, when pronounced atyanta , slips into the full cerebral
double c (which is pronounced cch). Cf . paccaya (see Note 11).;
14 , NIPPHANNA, PARINIPPHANNA : DETERMINED,
PREDETERMINED,
(XI . 7 ; XXIII . 5) .
This word is, according to the Abliidhdnappadlpikasiicl,
derived from the root 'pad,' 'to go,' through its causal
verb 'padeti,' 'to move or set agoing.' The prefix 'ni '
alters the meaning of ' being set agoing' into ' being
accomplished' (siddhiy ag). Ledi Sadaw qualifies this
meaning by ' accomplished by causes, such as karma, etc.'
(kammadlh i paccayeh i nipphaditag) . Now
karma is psychologically reduced to volition (cetana>
Hence anything accomplished by volition is ' accomplished
by causes/ or ' determined/ And i f karma happens to be past,
the word under discussion implies ' predetermination.' This
term is technically applied to the eighteen kinds of material
qualities,
1
the remaining ten, in the dual classification of
matter, being termed anipphannarupa's , or 'un-pre-
determined.'
The following quotation from the Abhidhammavatara
(p. 74 PTS. Ed.) is in point:—'(It may be urged that) if these
(ten) be undetermined, they would be unconditioned. But
how can they be unconditioned when they are changing
their aspects (vikaratta) ? These (un-) determined, too,
are conditioned. Thus the conditionedness of the (un-)
determined may be understood.' Prom the Buddhist point
of view, Nibbana alone is unconditioned. Therefore the
Conditioned includes both the ' determined' and the
' undetermined.'
The Katha XXIII. 5 indicates the general use of the
term parinipphanna . The Burmese translators do
not distinctively bring out the force of the prefix 'pari. '
A paticcasamuppannadhamma , i.e., anything that
springs into being through a cause, is necessarily con-
ditioned (sankhata). And one of the characteristic
marks of the conditioned is impermanence. The universal
1
See Abhidhammavatara, loc. cit. ; Compendium, p. 156.
proposition—4
Whatever is impermanent is ill'—is a Bud-
dhist thesis. Mind and matter are both impermanent and
are, therefore, ill. In other words, our personality — or
more analytically, personality minus craving—constitutes
the First Ariyan Fact of 111 . Ill, thus distributed, is
determined. But the opponent errs in regarding the
content of the term parinipphann a as exhausted by
11 1 proper. By this unnecessary restriction he errs in his
application of the contrary term aparinipphann a to
other factors of life.
Since a Dhamma or phenomenon other than Nibbana is
conditioned, it follows that each link in the chain of causa-
tion is conditioned. Takemind-and-body (namarupa):—
this we have shown to be a paticcasamuppann a
because it comes into being through causes. And though
it may also act as a paticcasamuppad a or causal
antecedent in turn, it is not determined as such, i.e., qua
cause. Dhammathitat a is nothing more than a
paticcasamuppad a stated in an abstract form. Now
in XI. 7 the opponent regards ' the state of being a cause'
as different from the causal element and, therefore, as
determined separately from the thing itself. In other
words, the opponent holds that causality or causation itself,
connoted by the term dhammathitata , is determined.
Again, aniccat a and jarata , as mere aspects of
' determined?
matter, are two of the admittedly anipphan-
narupa's . And by analogy, aniccat a of mind would
be equally undetermined. In fact, aniccata , as a mere
mark of the conditioned, is not specially determined, as the
opponent, in XI. 8, would have it to be.
15 . WILLING, ANTICIPATING-, AIMING.
(VIII. 9, § 1, p. 221 f.)
Since sending this discourse to press, we have discovered
that the triad:—'willing, anticipating, aiming' (cetana,
patthana, panidhi), so often in the present work added to
the four other mental activities: 'adverting, ideating,co-
ordinated application, attending,' occurs in the Anguttara-
Nikaya, v. 212 f. E.g. 'when a person has all the
attributes of the Ariyan Eightfold Path, coupled with true
insight and emancipation, whatever he does in accordance
with the rightness of his views, what he wills, anticipates,
aims at, whatever his activities:-all these will conduce to
that which is desirable, lovely, pleasant, good and happy.'
No comments:
Post a Comment